Philosophy of Science: Economics as a Philosophical Concern

In recent decades, the debates on the meaning and content of experimental analysis have been extensively discussed in philosophy. The discussions of the implications overlapped physical examination to social sciences such as economics.

This study’s fundamental position involves the factors considered scientific, their theories’ viability, and their relationship to the truth. One of the critical aspects regarded as problematic to philosophers is the relevance and truthfulness of the experimental deductions of unobservable objects. Besides, the questions test the justifiability of the conclusions and their applicability. In evaluating the validity of theorems in fields such as economics, it is essential to integrate past and modern scientific concepts from a philosophical perspective because the combination provides an inclusive and broad view.

Several ideas have been suggested in the past regarding the application of knowledge of economics. Some of the approaches involved assumptions that explained the relevant phenomenon in its domain. Some of the notions include the idea that theories are the main content of science (Bunge, 2017). As such, a mature experimental observation ideally produces a single identifiable explanation for the event.

However, in general practice, different arguments can arise from a single analysis. Consequently, the remainder is to unify the proposals in one account. Another assumption is that the fundamental scientific concepts should have clear definitions of the particular conditions for the given line of thought. Other questions considered involve the notion that explanation and confirmation have logic (Hausman, 2017). Concerning the limitations of the social sciences, the old theories have proposals whose applicability requires critical review amidst the data evolution in the contemporary populace.

The modern perspective of scientific theory and its methodology has advanced and discredited the old systems of thought. Some of the concerns raised are based on such assumptions as conceptual analysis, which elaborate that not all concepts are definable. Additionally, the classification of ideas as being science or pseudoscience is perceived to be misplaced and misleading. The former scheme overly focused on abstract models, which the current version has transformed by a range of exhibiting activities. One such development was the growth of enormous computing power where representations could be compared against a set of extensive data (Hardt, 2017).

Others included the rising integration of economics in other research disciplines, the rise of Game Theory, and heavy reliance on empirical experimentation of economics’ concepts. However, these developments should not be viewed as paradigm shifts from Kuhn’s perspective.

The transformation is based on the new modeling that is supported solely by empirical data. The view is founded on assumptions of putative logic of confirmation and holism, which leads to change primarily in their fundamental ontologies (Dietrich & List, 2016). The assessment provides useful information that scientists make implicit metaphysical reference to their observations of nature’s perceived observable features (Dietrich & List, 2016).

Experimental procedures focus more on mathematical structures in designing experiments and evaluating observations more than the semantic part of theories. Similar to physics, economics has replaced the initial abstract models with arithmetic-based schemes. Computational models differ from the previous forms, especially in their purpose. In essence, they provide detailed empirical investigation, although they still obtain information from earlier structures which focused more on uniqueness and stability.

Scientific knowledge extensively borrows from rigorous observations of factual experience, which is usually acquired from experimental procedures. In economics, there are various theories developed over the years, which account for its numerous models. One such is the number-crunching approach. It argues that there is a possibility that sciences may not experience any significant technological growth except for the continued development of computational capacity.

The expansion of the magnitude of data evaluation is due to endless innovations in micro-processing. The view emphasizes the need for economists to return to qualitative research, richer in empirical understanding than quantitative examination (Sætra, 2018). However, the arithmetic oriented approach has solved several such problems as the representation of complex reality. The previous methodology required the immense imagination capacity of the economist to distinguish between different possible parametric outcomes.

The mathematically oriented technique reduces over-reliance on abstraction and promotes empirical verification of hypotheses. Currently, the application of artificial intelligence is rapidly transforming the field, and the burgeoning computational capacity is creating econometric techniques (Symons & Alvarado, 2016). Nonetheless, the solution to problems with computers is limited to economists’ understanding of such issues to comprehend the requisite programming modes. However, the discipline might become boring when everything is computerized, although arithmetic provides investigators with exceptional accuracy.

Additionally, other important questions tend to study the theoretical laws and whether they have proper logical forms. They also include asking the theoretical principles on the given approach and its relevant logical forms. Furthermore, the inquiries can include finding out the truthfulness of the said fundamentals and their relationship to the reported observations. Kuhn’s ideology reports that science is an inherently communal engagement for society. As such, its variations with other disciplines are on how a community functions. The established facts of the study are equally analyzed to determine the researcher’s bias during conclusions. Other factors include the meaning and consequences of rationality and the type of normative evaluation of economic policies and outcomes.

To conclude, economics’ overall philosophical concern is based on how it operates within its metaphysical realm and connection with morality. It addresses the problems on the scope of economics and the methodologies used in its examination. The techniques used in the study apply to its assessment since these methods demonstrate epistemic reliability. Ethics and metaphysics are somewhat disregarded in economics, although epistemology is highly valued in the philosophy of science. The experimental analysis’s primary shift is the diversion from abstract information to computational data examination, which has improved accuracy.

References

Bunge, M. (2017). Philosophy of science: Volume 1, From problem to theory. Routledge.

Dietrich, F., & List, C. (2016). Mentalism versus behaviorism in economics: A philosophy-of-science perspective. Economics & Philosophy, 32(2), 249−281.

Hardt, Ł. (2017). Economics without laws: Towards a new philosophy of economics. Springer.

Hausman, D. M. (2017). Philosophy of economics: A retrospective reflection. Review of Economic Philosophy, 18(2), 185−202.

Sætra, H. S. (2018). Science as a vocation in the era of big data: The philosophy of science behind big data and humanity’s continued part in science. Integrative Psychological and Behavioral Science, 52(4), 508−522. Web.

Symons, J., & Alvarado, R. (2016). Can we trust big data? Applying philosophy of science to software. Big Data & Society, 3(2).

Cite this paper

Select style

Reference

StudyCorgi. (2022, May 4). Philosophy of Science: Economics as a Philosophical Concern. https://studycorgi.com/philosophy-of-science-economics-as-a-philosophical-concern/

Work Cited

"Philosophy of Science: Economics as a Philosophical Concern." StudyCorgi, 4 May 2022, studycorgi.com/philosophy-of-science-economics-as-a-philosophical-concern/.

* Hyperlink the URL after pasting it to your document

References

StudyCorgi. (2022) 'Philosophy of Science: Economics as a Philosophical Concern'. 4 May.

1. StudyCorgi. "Philosophy of Science: Economics as a Philosophical Concern." May 4, 2022. https://studycorgi.com/philosophy-of-science-economics-as-a-philosophical-concern/.


Bibliography


StudyCorgi. "Philosophy of Science: Economics as a Philosophical Concern." May 4, 2022. https://studycorgi.com/philosophy-of-science-economics-as-a-philosophical-concern/.

References

StudyCorgi. 2022. "Philosophy of Science: Economics as a Philosophical Concern." May 4, 2022. https://studycorgi.com/philosophy-of-science-economics-as-a-philosophical-concern/.

This paper, “Philosophy of Science: Economics as a Philosophical Concern”, was written and voluntary submitted to our free essay database by a straight-A student. Please ensure you properly reference the paper if you're using it to write your assignment.

Before publication, the StudyCorgi editorial team proofread and checked the paper to make sure it meets the highest standards in terms of grammar, punctuation, style, fact accuracy, copyright issues, and inclusive language. Last updated: .

If you are the author of this paper and no longer wish to have it published on StudyCorgi, request the removal. Please use the “Donate your paper” form to submit an essay.