Theorist in the Field of Child Psychology

Jean Piaget made great contribution to child psychology and development of the new approaches and concepts in this sphere. The benefit of Piaget’s theory is that young children are far more able than the theorist gave them credit for. Though, it seems that there is also a hazard of overestimating the abilities of young children, and that perhaps they lack the requisite mental flexibility or possibly the logic for solving certain problems, such as conservation. Even in the satiation of conservation, although, it seems a child younger than Piaget had supposed is able to give the correct judgment if the dilemma is presented in the right way. Collectively, then, studies investigating Piaget’s theories have served to shape the distinction between preoperational and concrete operational thinking (Berk, 2008). So although researchers can argue that young children can have difficulty with the logic of certain problems, it now looks doubtful that these errors all fit together neatly to suggest an overarching multipart of thought process we could call preoperational intellect as described by Piaget.

Jean Piaget was born in Switzerland in 1896, and died in 1980. Piaget’s early curiosity was in biology and his first publication, which was on that very subject, appeared when he was 10 years old. A few years later he was invited to be guardian of hellfish at a natural history museum in Geneva. This was a propose he had to decline, since he was still attending secondary school only. At age of 21 yeas old, Piaget was awarded a doctoral degree for a paper he wrote about hellfish. It was at this point that the great psychologist switched his interest to cognitive development, when he began working on the thought that a crucial ingredient in the relationship between people and their environment is intelligence. In order to acquire insight into this intelligence, Piaget concentrated on the most intelligent animals of all: human beings. The theorist believed that insight into the natural world of intelligence could best be gained by studying its development. Therefore Piaget became a cognitive developmentalist. At the time of his death, the theorist had written over 40 books on cognitive development, and over a100 articles on the same subject. This was in addition to many other publications on hellfish, philosophy and education. The theorist also tried his hand at science fiction: during the emotional turmoil of his adolescence, he expressed some of his emotions in a novel which was publihed in 1917 (Baldwin, 2000).

in general, Piaget suggested children pass through a series of stages on the way to cognitive adulthood (Baldwin, 2000). His idea was that cognitive development is not a permanent process, dependent upon the accumulation of more and more information and knowledge; his observation was that cognitive development proceeds not by slow evolution, but by way of cognitive revolution. As the child shifts onto a new and more sophisticated stage of intelligence, he heds many of the old cognitive limitations at a single sweep. Modern researchers look at what, according to Piaget, it is that enables children to grow through the stages (i.e. the mechanism of development) (Baldwin 2000).

Piaget states that age ranges for the stages, but these were only intended as a rough guide. The more important issues is that the order of the stages is supposed to be fixed and invariant. Piaget’s opinion was that each stage served as the foundation for the later stage, so according to the theory, it would be impossible to miss any stage. To Piaget, missing a stage would be similar to building the second storey of a dwelling without first building the first floor. For Piaget, addition is essential for carrying tens and also for subtotals in order to calculate the grand total. In this case, addition is a precondition for long multiplication. According to Piaget’s theory, succeeding through one stage is a precondition for shifting onto the subsequent stage. Though, if one enjoyed the benefit of suitable experiences, it might be possible to evolve through the stages more rapidly than one who was less fortunate (Baldwin 2000).

The first stage is a progress from childhood or infancy. The stage gets its meaning from the notion that the child has sensory experiences (can see, hear, feel, taste, smell) and can be in motion (motor movements), but there is little cognition mediating the two actions. For instance, Piaget’s opinion was that the child has no conception of the permanent world which has an existence separately of the child. The researcher had a great many things to say about this stage, but modem scientists focus on his ideas about the development of the thought of object permanence (Berk, 2008). Piaget claimed that at birth people are in a state of solipsism. In other words, Piaget was making the amazing claim that babies cannot distinguish between self and not self.

As a result, childs have no understanding of the permanent existence of things (i.e. objects) other than the self. Though, after having passed through a series of sub-stages by the age of 24 months the child will differentiate between himself and surroundings, will be capable of mental imagery and will have an understanding of symbols. In all, Piaget listed 6 sub-stages of infancy. The first relevant one is Stage 3, which lasts from 4 to 8 months of age. At this age, the child is perfectly capable of grasping and picking up things such as a rattle (Baldwin, 2000). Given this ability, parents can play a game with the child, in which they take his rattle and put it in various places, just within the child’s reach. Providing the rattle is within reach (many children of this age cannot crawl yet), the child might enter into the game and retrieve it. Though, if we put the rattle within reach but right away cover it with a cloth, even though the covered object is in full view, the child will not reach out. Instead he will switch attention to something else (Berk, 2008).

Piaget claimed that the child does have the deftness to remove the cloth, then grab the rattle. Piaget claimed, so that the child’s breakdown to get back the rattle from under the cloth was not due to a lack of skill. Instead, The researcher suggested that when an item is hidden from view, the child no longer conceives of its existence. At this stage, when the child can no longer directly sense an object, the object no longer exists as far as the child is concerned. If parents remove the cloth, the child will then recognize the rattle and grasp it. So the child can recognize objects he is familiar with, but when objects are no longer accessible to the mind, they no longer have any existence for the child. According to Piaget, this is because the child is unable to conjure up an image of the object in its physical absence. Oneimplication of this radical claim is that although the child recognizes and is familiar with her mother, when the mother leaves the room, from that moment to the parents’ return, the child no longer has any notion of the adult. To the young child, the mother is just an image which goes through a curious sequence of appearing and disappearing (Berk, 2008).

During Stage 4 of infancy (8 to 12 months), the child’s concept of object permanence develops to the point that the child appears to possess a primitive notion that objects may exist even if they cannot be sensed directly. At this development stage, the child will have no difficulty in retrieving a rattle hidden beneath a cloth. On the face of it, some researchers may think that if the child searches for something hidden from view, this must mean that the child knows about that hidden thing even when it cannot be seen. Though, Piaget would have others believe that the child is still dominated by what he senses, and in particular, at this stage of development, his actions (i.e. motor movements). An older child, in contrast, relies much more on mental imagery. According to Piaget, once the child has retrieved the rattle from under the cloth, he then understands the life of the rattle, in terms of her action in retrieving it (Baldwin 2000). Piaget demonstrated this with a simple test, known as the A-B task.

Piaget spread out two cloths side by side in front of the child. He then hid the rattle under the left cloth (cloth A), and, as expected, the child pulled away the cloth and grabbed the rattle. Piaget repeated this a further two times. Then, on the fourth trial, in full view of the child, Piaget put the rattle under the right-hand cloth (cloth B). The child searched under the left cloth, as before, and on failing to find the rattle there, ceased searching and switched attention to something else. What makes this finding particularly abnormal is that the shape of the rattle remains apparent under the right-hand cloth throughout. In Stage 4, according to the psychologist, once the child has brought about the reappearance of the object by the act of searching, he then understands the reappearance of the object in terms of the specific actions involved in the investigation. In other words, the child has little notion of the existence of the object independent of his own actions. To the child, the existence of the object means a sequence of hand and arm movements (Berk, 2008).

Current trends and findings involve Mooney (2000) research on childhood and Campbell and Bickhard (2003). Following Piaget’s theory, these researchers state that the child no longer understands the object just in terms of his own actions. Though, Piaget underlines that children still have difficulty understanding the existence of objects they cannot directly experience, since they apparently have no notion of the movement of an unseen object. To demonstrate this, the researcher put the rattle under the left-hand cloth, and then, before the child was given an opportunity to search, Piaget also put an up-side-down bowl under that cloth, covering the rattle with the bowl as he did so (Berk, 2008). The researcher then pulled the bowl from under the cloth, with the rattle hidden inside, and moved it under the right-hand cloth. He then removed the bowl, and placed it in full view, where it could be seen to be empty, having deposited the rattle under the right-hand cloth. The child, who had been watching all this, was then allowed to begin searching. The child searched under the left-hand cloth, where the rattle wasput to begin with, but on failing to find it there, ceased searching and switched thought to something else (Baldwin 2000).

During Stage 5, the child is no longer dominated by her own actions in understanding the existence of objects. Though, it seems the child continues to have great difficulty in understanding objects which are not sensed in a straight line, since he seems unable to comprehend the possibility of movement of the object when it is hidden from view. Older children presumably understand that if the rattle was not under the left-hand cloth, it must have traveled with the bowl to the right-hand cloth. This is an understanding which seems to be beyond a child aged between 12 and 18 months. The cause, according to Piaget, is because the child has difficulty in imagining the object to have its own autonomous existence; the child struggles to understand that the object is not directly experienced, it is possible for things to go on happening to it, such as moving from one place to another (Campbell and Bickhard 2003).

At this stage, the child at last is able to imagine of the existence of an object independently of the self, and consequently is no longer in a state of solipsism. The child now understands that on the one hand there is the outside world, and on the other hand, distinct from that, is the self. The child achieves this, according to the researcher, by acquiring the facility of mental imagery. The child is able to generate a mental picture of things, and what might happen to those things, even though these events cannot be experienced in a straight line. As a result, the child no longer has difficulty locating an object which is hidden and then shifted, providing it is easy to work out where it was moved to. That is, the child no longer has any complexity with the task he failed during Stage 5 of childhood.

The achievement of mental imagery is a revolutionary point in the child’s life, which heralds the change to a whole new stage of development in the broadest meaning. It is at this point that the child is viewed as succeeding from the sensori-motor stage of childhood to the preoperational stage of early childhood. The critics admit that the most important consequence of psychological imagery is that it makes possible the use of symbols. A mental image need not be a mental replica of the thing it is concerned with. If the image is about something in the world, but is not a mental replica of that thing, then it is a symbol of that thing. According to Piaget, it is no coincidence that at the end of infancy the child begins to develop proficiency in that most powerful of human symbols, language (Campbell and Bickhard 2003). The rational achievements which become possible with the aid of language in its various forms are literally unimaginable. For instance, consider some of the remarkable progress in technology and science this century (Berk, 2008).

Most of the facts mentioned above would have been impossible without mathematics and written language to work out and communicate the ideas responsible for this progress. A significant aspect of Piaget’s thinking becomes clear at this point. The psychologist stressed that intellectual growth underpins language development in important ways, not the other way round; a capacity for mental imagery permits proficiency in use of symbols, one form of which happens to be language. It hardly needs to be stated that language enables more efficient problem solving (Berk, 2008). Though, symbolic activity other than the use of a recognizable language may also facilitate problem solving (Brearley and Hitchfield 2002).

In order to illustrate some cases, Piaget tells of how his own child, who was nearing the end of childhood, solved the problem of how to retrieve a chain hidden inside a matchbox. When given the matchbox, the child made a awkward attempt to open the box but failed. He then paused, opened and closed her mouth a few times whilst gazing at the matchbox, and then smoothly opened the box to retrieve the chain. According to the psychologist, his child registered the way in which the matchbox opened symbolically in her mouth movement. After working out the problem in this way, he was able to proceed and open the box with no difficulty (Singer and Revenson 2003). This example shows that Piaget supposed it is not the case that language makes possible symbolic problem-solving activity (Baldwin, 2000).

The kid can solve problems symbolically without language. Though, no doubt Piaget would accept that, given the possible for symbolic activity, language then becomes a useful tool for this purpose. Symbolic activity is most evident in young children’s pretend play. Here researchers find children pretending that bananas are telephones, that chairs are cars, that shoe boxes are television sets, and so on. Watching young children engage in pretend play gives the impression that they are exercising their newly acquired symbolic ability purely for the delight of it. There is reason to suppose that the symbolic element of pretend play is not just a manifestation of having reached a developmental milestone. Some critics argue persuasively that pretend play actually promotes cognitive development in various ways (Brearley and Hitchfield 2002).

Current trends and theories suggest that the young child is overwhelmed with egocentrism. This term might seem a little confusing, because the psychologist did not use the term according to its direct meaning. In ordinary jargon, researchers call someone ‘egocentric’ to mean that they are selfish and inconsiderate of others (Singer and Revenson 2003). Modern psychological application of the word, in contrast, means a cognitive limitation which prevents the child from seeing things from somebody else’s point of view. It is not really suitable to say the young child is inconsiderate, since it is claimed that the young child is incapable of understanding that another person might have a viewpoint different from her own. In this case, ‘different viewpoint’ is used both in a literal sense, as in failing to understand that objects look different from different perspectives, and in a conceptual sense, as in failing to understand that people may hold opinions, beliefs, etc. different from her own. Intimately linked with egocentrism is a profound inability to understand and relate principles to the world. The young child’s grasp of things is intuitive and highly subjective, rather than logical and objective. Consequently, the child’s thinking is dominated by surface form, rather than by underlying principles. The best way to illustrate this is with examples of tests which a preoperational child fails (Piaget, 2000).

Today, the best known proof of breakdown to understand and apply these theories during the preoperational stage is in the breakdown to conserve. In this sense, ‘conservation’ has nothing to do with green politics, but rather is to do with the understanding that transformation of appearance need not result in alteration of the underlying reality. The underlying reality remains steady, and therefore is conserved, despite the transformation in appearance. It seems that, instead of attending to a principle (i.e. operation), such as ‘none was added or taken away, so the amount of water must be the same’, young children were seduced by, and centered on, the increased height of the water level in the thin glass. The child gives an intuitive answer instead of working out the correct answer on the basis of an underlying principle. That is, the child fails to ‘decentre’.

Young children also show a breakdown to conserve on a variety of other tasks, some of which we will now take a look at. In the conservation of length task, we show the child two pencils of the same length, and begin by aligning the points so that equality of length becomes apparent. After the child agrees they are the same length, we move one of the pencils slightly, so that its point protrudes above that of the other by about a centimeter. Preoperational children will judge they are no longer the same size, and point to one of the pencils, claiming it is bigger. In the conservation of mass task, we make two balls of plasticize the same size, and, after the child agrees that they are the same size, we roll one into a sausage shape. Preoperational children usually judge that the sausage shape is bigger and has more plasticize in it. In the conservation of number task, we spread out two rows of, for example, ten counters, in one-to-one correspondence (Brearley and Hitchfield 2002).

Piaget stated that there were many errors young children make which he claimed are signs of preoperational, non-principled, non-logical thinking. We shall consider just two more of these. First is the difficulty young children have with class inclusion. We spread out, for example, seven Lego bricks, five red and two blue. In this example, the overall class of bricks includes the subclasses of red bricks and blue bricks. The child knows that all seven items are in the class of bricks, because if we ask how many bricks there are, they have no difficulty in answering with ‘seven’. We then ask, ‘Are there more bricks or more red bricks?’ Preoperational kids answer with, ‘More red bricks.’ According to Piaget, the young baby concentrates on the greater number of red bricks compared with blue bricks, and as a result fails to operate on the principle that the class of bricks must be bigger than the subclass of red bricks, because the class of bricks includes both red and blue bricks. Finally, we come to transitive inference (Mooney, 2000).

Piaget presented a task which involves the same problem in principle, but which to adults and older children seems absurdly simple. Reseacgers show the child two towers made of lego, one a little taller than the other. Just by looking, it is impossible to tell which is the taller, for two reasons. First, the towers are in different parts of the room, so they can’t both be taken in at a glance. Second, they are on different levels, for example, one on a coffee table and one on the floor. The comparison reveals that one tower is bigger than the stick, whilst the other is smaller. Preoperational kids are very poor at this task. They seem to have no idea what to do with the stick, and even if we do the measuring for them, they do not reliably give the correct answer, that the tower taller than the stick is bigger than the tower shorter than the stick (Mooney, 2000).

Following Piaget, this is yet another case of young children failing to operate on a principle, which, in this case, would be ‘if this tower is bigger than the stick, and that tower is shorter than the stick, then this tower must be bigger than that tower’. It is very unusual indeed to find a young child who does not make the errors described in these pages, though some people, as you will discover later, disagree with Piaget’s interpretation of the findings. The tests are very simple to carry out, and you can demonstrate the errors very easily by performing them on young children in your family. It is especially interesting to introduce modifications to the procedure of the tests to see if it helps children to get the correct answer (Ginsburg and Opper 2000).

A traditional example of egocentrism can be found in the ‘three mountains task’. Researchers sit the child in front of a model landscape of three mountains located side by side. During this stage, but not during the concrete operational stage, the child is able to solve the transitive inference problem on a purely mental level; no real items need be involved. The adolescent can work out that if x is bigger than y and x is smaller than z, then the smallest altogether must be y. These characters need have no value in the real world for the adolescent to find the correct solution. In solving the problem, the adolescent can mentally manipulate the symbols in a way that is purely formal and logical. Piaget suggested that the ideal is when assimilation and accommodation contribute equally. If either dominates, then there may be a problem. An example of over-assimilation is pretence. In this case the child displays little adaptation to the world, but instead interprets the world in her own highly idiosyncratic way (Flavell 2002).

According to Piaget, people are intrinsically motivated to exercise our schemes, particularly when the schemes are newly acquired, and this process is not dependent on external reward (Phillips, 2003). Consequently, there is plenty of opportunity for assimilation and accommodation to occur, and therefore plenty of opportunity for schemes to develop. In other words, there is plenty of chance for the growth of intelligence, given the way in which growth supposedly takes place. As the scheme’s breadth of application increases, so the separation in each mode of application increases (Berk, 2008). There comes a point when the modes of application of a method are so diverse that it is no longer a single scheme but rather a series of schemes within a certain genre. For instance, the system for holding a paintbrush is in some respects quite different from the systems for holding the steering wheel of a car, yet both are descendants of the innate grasping scheme (Flavell 2002). Systems and structures may also be coordinated, or brought together, into a giant scheme to perform complicated actions. Researchers admit that driving a car is a useful case of this: steering, gears, brake, clutch and accelerator, just to gve name some of the individual schemes comprising the overall system of ‘driving’ (Ginsburg and Opper 2000).

In sum, the theories and principles developed by Piaget became a core of child psychology and development science. At this point things may seem reasonably simple, that schemes develop, and this is influenced in a significant way by assimilation and accommodation. Piaget supposes that underlying each stage is a new category of scheme. In the sensori-motor stage, the only signs are motor schemes as in throwing rattles, crawling and so on. In the preoperational phase, the child has schemes which are not just motor, but may involve mental imagery also. At the concrete operational phase, signs may proceed through a series of mental actions perhaps in the way a computer runs a program, to arrive at the solution to a problem in a principled and logical way. In the formal operational phase, the same maintains, except the problem need have no physical reality. The non-conserving child entertains the belief that tallness and quantity are intimately linked, so he will think that a tall column of liquid contains more than a short one. That seems like a perfectly reasonable belief to hold, and no doubt most adults think in a similar way.

References

Baldwin, A. L. (2000). Behavior and Development in Childhood. New York: Dryden Press.

Brearley, Molly, and Elizabeth Hitchfield. A (2002). Guide to Reading Piaget. New York: Schocken Books.

Berk, L. E. (2008). Child Development 8th edition.

Campbell, R.L. and Bickhard, M.H. (2003) Knowing levels and developmental stages, Basel: Karger.

Ginsburg, Herbert, and Sylvia Opper. (2000). Piaget’s Intellectual Development. New Jersey: Prentice-Hall, Inc.

Flavell John H. (2002). The Developmental Psychology of Jean : Piaget, Princeton: D. Van Nostrand Co., Inc.

Mooney, C.G. (2000). Theories of Childhood: An Introduction to Dewey, Montessori, Erikson, Piaget & Vygotsky. Redleaf Press.

Phillips, John L., Jr. (2003). The Origins of Intellect: Piaget’s Theory. San Francisco: W. H. Freeman & Company.

Piaget, J. (2000). The Psychology Of The Child. Basic Books; 2 edition.

Singer, D.J., Revenson, T.A. (2003). A Piaget Primer: How a Child Thinks; Revised EditionPlume; Rev Sub edition.

Cite this paper

Select style

Reference

StudyCorgi. (2021, November 21). Theorist in the Field of Child Psychology. https://studycorgi.com/theorist-in-the-field-of-child-psychology/

Work Cited

"Theorist in the Field of Child Psychology." StudyCorgi, 21 Nov. 2021, studycorgi.com/theorist-in-the-field-of-child-psychology/.

* Hyperlink the URL after pasting it to your document

References

StudyCorgi. (2021) 'Theorist in the Field of Child Psychology'. 21 November.

1. StudyCorgi. "Theorist in the Field of Child Psychology." November 21, 2021. https://studycorgi.com/theorist-in-the-field-of-child-psychology/.


Bibliography


StudyCorgi. "Theorist in the Field of Child Psychology." November 21, 2021. https://studycorgi.com/theorist-in-the-field-of-child-psychology/.

References

StudyCorgi. 2021. "Theorist in the Field of Child Psychology." November 21, 2021. https://studycorgi.com/theorist-in-the-field-of-child-psychology/.

This paper, “Theorist in the Field of Child Psychology”, was written and voluntary submitted to our free essay database by a straight-A student. Please ensure you properly reference the paper if you're using it to write your assignment.

Before publication, the StudyCorgi editorial team proofread and checked the paper to make sure it meets the highest standards in terms of grammar, punctuation, style, fact accuracy, copyright issues, and inclusive language. Last updated: .

If you are the author of this paper and no longer wish to have it published on StudyCorgi, request the removal. Please use the “Donate your paper” form to submit an essay.